Suppose that we wanted to construct a mathematical universe where all objects were computable in some sense. How would we do it?
Well, we could certainly allow the set into our universe: natural numbers are the most basic computational objects there are. (Notation: I’ll use to refer to when we’re considering it as part of the universe we’ll building, and just when we’re talking about the set of natural numbers in the “real” world.) What should we take as our set of functions from to ? Since we want to admit only computable things, we should let be the set of computable functions from to , which we can represent non-uniquely by their indices (i.e., by the programs which compute them).
(For clarity, I’ll use the following notation for computable functions: denotes the partial function from to computed by the th Turing machine. Given , it is possible that the computation never halts; in that case, I’ll write and say that is undefined. If it does halt, I’ll write and say that is defined. If it halts, then it yields an output . To indicate what it is, I’ll write or .)
So, we’ve decided that should equal . What should equal? At this point, there is a slight subtlety: It’s not simply the set of computable functions from (considered as a subset of ) to (considered as ), because we would like to only admit those functions from to that return the same number when given inputs which represent the same element of .
Therefore, we’ll let be the set of such that, for all , , and whenever are such that for all , , then .
We can similarly define , except that there are now two places where we should take into account that we consider equivalent if for all , : We’ll let be the set of such that, whenever are equivalent in the aforementioned sense, and are defined and equivalent in the aforementioned sense.
In a similar fashion, we can define and so on; these sets are called the sets of hereditarily computable functions.
Can we generalize this construction to a category that incorporates all possible computable representations of real objects? More ambitiously, can we generalize to a category that is a genuine mathematical universe in the sense that questions like “Does the Riemann Hypothesis hold in this category?” are meaningful? The answer, due to Martin Hyland, is yes.
This material is from Jaap van Oosten‘s book “Realizability: A Categorical Perspective” (link to Preface, Introduction and Table of Contents). Unfortunately, I don’t know of a freely available explanation of the effective topos on the web, which is part of the reason why I’m writing this blog entry. (If you know of one, please leave a comment. Edit: Found one.) However, the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy has a pretty good section on the realizability interpretation of intuitionistic logic, on which Hyland’s effective topos is based.
Back to the math. Notice that what we did in the case was the following: Although we represented the computable functions as a subset of , we still kept the “real” set hiding around in the background: we used it to determine what the appropriate elements of should be: If two elements of represented the same element of the “real set” , then an element of should assign the same number to both of them.
That suggests a generalization. Let an assembly be a pair , where is a set, and is a function from to , the power set of . We think of as assigning to each element of its computable representations. We let a morphism between two assemblies and be a function from to such that there is an such that, whenever , and , .
With these morphisms, the class of assemblies forms a category. Let and be two assemblies. Then they have a direct product given by , where and is a pairing function. They have an exponential given by , where .
If we let be the assembly , where , then the iterated exponential objects of correspond precisely to our initial definition of the sets of hereditarily computable objects above.
This is all great, but we still can’t call the category of assemblies a mathematical universe. Why not? Well, in the real world, we ask questions like “Is the Riemann Hypothesis true?”, “Is Goldbach’s conjecture true”, etc., but we don’t yet know how to ask questions like “Is the Riemann Hypothesis true in the category of assemblies?” any more than it makes sense to ask whether or not the Riemann Hypothesis is true in the group or in the number 17. What we need is a way to interpret statements being true or not in this category.
In turning the category of assemblies into one in which we can interpret logical statements, there are three considerations, each of which builds on the previous ones.
- The object of truth values should have more than two elements. Let’s step back to the ordinary category of sets for a moment. Say we have two sets and and an injection from to . Given , what is the truth value of the proposition that is in the image of ? Well, I don’t know, but it’s clearly either or . But in the category of assemblies it’s more complicated due to the computational information we have lying around. Say that we have an injective morphism from an assembly to an assembly . Given , now what is the truth value of the proposition that is in the image of ? What if there is a such that but ? Without resolving the issue now, one plausible answer is that the truth value should be the set of indices of all computable functions taking to , so that the more “alike” and , the more “true” the proposition is, and furthermore this “alikeness” is represented in a computational way. So, a working hypothesis is that the set of truth values should be something like .
- Objects should come equipped with an equivalence relation. In the category of assemblies, there is no question about whether or not two elements of a given object are equal. If we are making a category where the object of truth values is something like , however, we should allow that the proposition that different elements are equal has a truth value in that object, rather than in the classical set of truth values. Therefore, objects should be something like , where is a set and is a map from to . (We can represent an assembly as the object in our new category where and if ).
- Morphisms should be more general than functions. If we’re allowing objects to come equipped with some sort of equivalence relation, we will have to let morphisms be more general than functions: If is a morphism from and , and , then is also true to some degree. So morphisms should probably be some sort of relation on that resembles a function in some way.
Now, after listing all those (somewhat vague) considerations, I’ll describe the category that takes them into account. It’s called the Effective Topos and it was discovered/invented by Martin Hyland.
Description of the category
The objects of the effective topos are pairs where is a set and is a map from to . This map is required to satisfy the following properties:
- There must be a number such that for all if then .
- There must be a number such that for all if and then .
(In the above, stands for “symmetric” and stands for “transitive.”)
A morphism from to is represented by a function satisfying the following:
- There must be a number such that for all , if then where and .
- There must be a number such that for all , , if , , and , then .
- There must be a number such that for all , , if and then .
- There must be a number such that for all , if then .
(In the above, stands for “strict,” stands for “relational,” stands for “single-valued” and stands for “total.”)
We say that two such representations and are equivalent if there exist such that for all , , if then and conversely if then . (Thus, a morphism in the Effective Topos is actually an equivalence class of representations as above.)
Figuring out how to compose such morphisms is an exercise left to the websurfer.
Let and be two objects. Their direct product is given by where . To form the exponential , take the object , where in the definition of , you emulate the definition of a morphism given above.
The object of truth values (often denoted in any topos) is , where .
The object playing the role of a singleton set is where .
The map from to representing the truth value is given by the equivalence class of the map defined by .
The natural numbers object of the effective topos is , where and where .
Interpretation of logical formulas in the effective topos.
I’ll now describe how logical formulas can be interpreted in Hyland’s effective topos. If are variables intended to range over the objects respectively and is a formula with free variables from , then I’ll show how to find a map from to interpreting that formula. If , and thus the formula has no free variables and is a sentence, then the interpretation will give a map from to . We say that a sentence holds in the effective topos if its interpretation is equal to the map defined above.
The only atomic relation is equality, and the interpretation of atomic formulas is given by the component of the objects of the effective topos.
For clarity, assume that and contain only one free variable, and that it ranges over the object . If we know the interpretations of and already, then we have the following:
- is represented by the map taking to .
- is represented by the map taking to .
- is represented by the map taking to .
Now suppose that has two free variables ranging over and respectively, and I’ll show you how to interpret quantifiers.
- is represented by the map taking to .
- is represented by the map taking to .
Now, once we observe that we can interpret the power “set” of an object in the effective topos as the exponential , we know how to interpret all first- and higher-order sentences as holding or not in the effective topos.
Here are some interesting sentences given by Van Oosten that highlight some differences between the effective topos and the ordinary category of sets.
- Note that we may write the relation “” as a relation on in our language. Then the sentence is true in the effective topos.
- For every formula , where is a variable ranging over and is a variable ranging over , the sentence holds in the effective topos.
- We may construct the rationals and the reals in the effective topos just as we do in the category of sets. However, they have different properties. For example, in the effective topos the statement “There exists a bounded monotonic sequence in that does not converge to a limit.” holds, contradicting the Bolzano-Weierstrass theorem. Intuitively, this is because we can find a bounded, monotonic sequence converging to a real number whose binary expansion encodes the halting problem but such that every member of the sequence has a decidable binary expansion.
- The sentence holds in the effective topos.
- Similar to the above, we may can show that the intermediate value theorem fails in the effective topos.
- In the effective topos, the statement “All functions from to are continuous” holds.